Department of Political Studies - University of Catania
Jean Monnet Chair of European Comparative Politics
Jean Monnet Working Papers in Comparative and International Politics
Donatella M. Viola
London School of Economics
International
Relations and European Integration Theory:
The Role of the European Parliament
January 2000 - JMWP n° 26
Over
the past fifty years, the pace of European integration has often accelerated,
slowed or reversed itself in response to external political and economic
events, confirming or refuting the validity of various theoretical assumptions
and predictions. It is important, therefore, not to look at this phenomenon in
isolation, but within the realm of international relations and to consider the
European Union as part of a wider system, "a segment of international
society" (Taylor, 1996, 90). Conceptualizing European integration cannot
be seen exclusively as the application of detached and abstruse notions
relevant only to Western Europe, but in a much broader sense, as an important
component of the literature on world politics with its roots entrenched deep
in the history of political thought (Keohane and Nye, 1993, 384-401).
Winding through the maze of International Relations and European
integration theories can be a lengthy and arduous challenge. The following
overview, which is by no means exhaustive, intends to illustrate briefly the
major theoretical assumptions relevant to European integration and set them,
where possible, within the mainstream of International Relations theory, an
explicit linkage which is too rarely made. In order to further highlight their
relevance to this thesis, an attempt is also made to identify the role played
or to be played by the European Parliament within the various original
theoretical models, which are used as hermeneutic devises. Finally, variants
of relevant concepts are tailored to allow for a theoretical conceptualization
of political groups in the Europarliamentary environment.
[1]
The `Trilogy' of International Relations Theory
Three
main traditions have emerged in the history of political thought: realism
embodied by Niccolò Machiavelli and Thomas Hobbes, rationalism or
internationalism by Hugo Grotius and universalism or revolutionism by Immanuel
Kant.
[2]
However, these traditions "are not like three railroad tracks running
parallel into infinity" and tendencies have often surfaced merging their
characteristics. The above 'trilogy', largely followed, modified and contested,
remains a milestone in the study of International Relations (Wight and Porter,
1991, Bull, 1977, 1995).
In
the realist image, international relations are mostly characterized by warfare
of all against all, best illustrated in Hobbes' axiom Bellum omnium contra omnes. Hans Morgenthau elaborates further this
concept, claiming that:
International politics, like all politics, is a struggle for power.
Whatever the ultimate aims of international politics, power is always the
immediate aim; Regardless of the instrument employed, the ultimate aim of
foreign policy is always the same: to promote one's interests by changing the
mind of the opponent (Morgenthau, 1973, 27 and 333).
States
compete for power and, in such a confrontation, moral principles are the first
to be lost (Brown, 1992, 97). By considering national security as a priority,
realists are especially concerned with actual or potential conflict between
states. They advocate a state-centric view of international relations and
regard nation states and not international organizations as the only "durable
units" in society and the real motors of change (Weiler and Wessels,
1988, 238). Realism reflects the tenet that influential states hold the reins
of the world and bear direct responsibility for international order (Banks,
1985, 15). International organizations may aspire to the status of independent
actors, but their ambition has not so far been achieved to any significant
extent.
In the early 1970s, after having dominated for two decades, the theory
began to falter only to re-emerge invigorated under the emblem of neorealism
(Little, 1985, 74). Its proponents, including Kenneth Waltz, Robert Gilpin,
Stephen Krasner, George Modelski and Robert Tucker, explain state behaviour in
conditions of anarchy, while stressing the importance of structure within the
international system and how this may influence state conduct. For some
neorealists such as Robert Keohane, the modern world is woven into
interdependent relationships, but the term interdependence, like a web,
conveys the negative connotation of vulnerability which should be fought or at
least minimized. However, interdependence does not denote equality between the
parties since not all states are vulnerable to the same extent (Viotti and
Kauppi, 1993, 55-56). This coming to terms with interdependence was rejected
by theorists belonging to the orthodox realist tradition pursued by Waltz.
Both realists and neorealists, nevertheless, maintain a net distinction
between `high' and `low' politics where the former dominates the latter (Viotti
and Kauppi, 1993, 7).
In
the aftermath of the Second World War, the Schuman Plan, which catalysed the
reconciliation of two historical enemies, France and Germany, and the
consequent efforts to develop further economic, political and social relations
between Western European countries, represented for realists a serious anomaly
(Groom, 1990, 9-10). Any attempt at replacing the nation state system with
another form of supranational government was considered artificial and highly
hazardous, inevitably leading to its destruction and subordination to a third
power. In the realist logic, not only would the establishment of a
supranational European Union not enhance Europe's international capability,
but it would even deprive the nation state of this capacity (Weiler and
Wessels, 1988, 238-239).
Modern realists such as Kenneth Waltz and John Mearsheimer, therefore,
believed that the European integration process, embarked on mainly in reaction
to Cold War bipolarism, would come to a halt with the fall of the Iron Curtain
(Waltz, 1979, 70-71, Mearsheimer, 1990, 5-56). In the eyes of realists,
European integration can be justified by the fact that a more integrated and
institutionally elaborated international organization can better serve, at
least provisionally, national interests. As such, the EU embodying a
confederation of sovereign states becomes the instrument for the member states
to achieve their own national objectives (Cameron, 1992, 28-29). However,
should they no longer feel the necessity of this membership, the states
reserve the right to withdraw. The intergovernmental institutionalization of
EPC/CFSP is acceptable in as far as it cements existing interstate bargains.
This view is aptly outlined by Inis L. Claude:
It is evident that the long-term evolution as well as the current
functioning of the Community institutions is fundamentally a matter to be
determined by the national governments concerned. Supranationality has
contrived no genuine escape from sovereign states. It may be a step toward
federal unity, but it is a step taken by governments, which retain the capacity to decide whether to take
further steps forward, to stand still, or to retreat (Claude, 1964, 1965,
1971, 103).
a)
The Role of the European Parliament in the Realist Model
As
seen in the previous section, realism is hardly conducive with the
supranational development of the European integration, regarded as anathema
because it leads to an artificial system whereby the state loses the
prerogative of promoting its bias (Weiler and Wessels, 1988, 238). As such,
the realist thesis reaffirms the primacy of member states' governments and
excludes any significant functions for supranational organs including the
European Parliament. Realists argue that the general state of anarchy that
characterizes the EP as a multinational platform for discussion does not make
it a suitable and efficient decision-making institution, especially when
dealing with foreign policy issues. The view that "strong supranational
institutions are (..) the antithesis of intergovernmentalism" is not
fully shared by Andrew Moravcsik who maintains that they can instead serve the
purposes of the member states (Moravcsik, 1993, 507).
With
regard to the European Parliament's political groups, their interactions are
regarded by realists as a `zero-sum game', where the extent of the gain for
one side corresponds to the loss for the other (Viotti and Kauppi, 1993, 241).
It is obvious that one actor holds more power than another if it can
contribute more effectively to defining and shaping policy results. Its power
over a coalition decision can be confirmed when its unilateral revocation of
support means jeopardizing the feasibility of the coalition agreement. The
more potential coalitions a group can destroy the greater its bargaining power
(Raunio and Matti, 1995). The capacity of political groups to inspire and
define parliamentary policies can be assessed through the concept of power and
compromise in the light of `game' and `cooperative' theories.
[3]
Duncan Snidal's analysis of relative gains and patterns of cooperation
produces results relevant to the understanding of the dynamics of political
groups over policy-making within the European Parliament. Political groups
enhance their possibilities of safeguarding themselves by building coalitions
and generally the less well united their respective rivals are, the safer and
more powerful they are. If the political groups decide to cooperate, each of
them receives on every occasion a constant return to scale (Snidal, 1993, 176,
192).
Rationalism/Internationalism
Rationalism/internationalism,
exemplified in the work of Grotius, Descartes, Spinoza and Leibnitz,
emphasizes the exercise of reason as the unique basis for belief in contrast
with the passive acceptance of authority or spiritual revelation (Wight and
Porter, 1991, 13). It stresses the value of `international and
institutionalized intercourse' in the context of international society, whilst
it acknowledges the moral strain exerted on the decision-making process, the
pressure and distress of rationalizing political power and justifying the
recourse to war, by appealing to the principle of the choice of the `lesser
evil'. In the Grotian Societas quasi
politica et moralis diplomacy and trade prevail during the pacific
intervals by attempting to institutionalize interstate dealings. Rationalists
reject the `high-low' politics dichotomy and hierarchy and often regard
socio-economic issues as being as vital as military and foreign policy (Viotti
and Kauppi, 1993, 229).
[4]
It
is possible to locate within the rationalist tradition, albeit to different
degrees, four theories of European integration - functionalism,
neofunctionalism, pluralism and consociationalism - for reproducing the
Grotian image of `international society' and for their emphasis on
`international and institutionalized intercourse'. The various players are
assumed to find benefit through mutual interactions in what is defined as a
"variable - or positive sum game" (Mitrany cited in Viotti and
Kauppi, 1993, 241).
a.1)
Functionalism
Functionalism
is one of the traditional approaches of international integration which is
commonly associated with the rational school of thought for its characteristic
of surrendering ideology to "enlightened self-interest" under the
influence of economic growth, for its modest and pragmatic character of
adapting to changes, for its problem-solving approach and for contemplating
the primacy of economics in international relations as an antidote to the
application of traditional power politics (Wallace and Smith, 1995, 140,
Taylor, 1990, 126, 136 and Harrison, 1974, 28-29, 66). Yet, it can also be set
within the realm of revolutionism for its universalist vocation envisaging the
creation of a world society, for its ambition of bypassing the role of
national governments and gradually eliminating the nation states and for
reviving the concept of `historical determinism' present in the work of Comte
and Marx.
[5]
A functionalist reading of integration is neither based on traditional
national units nor aimed at the creation of a superimposing regional state, as
that would not solve the present discontents, but only perpetuate and magnify
dangerous political cleavages at a higher level (Pentland, 1973, 75-76, 149).
The telos is, rather, that of
establishing technical and depoliticized units specializing in specific
functions, which might lead to the creation of a world federation (Mutimer,
1994, 29). This entails the gradual demise and substitution of the
state-system by an administrative network that fulfils the needs of the
emergent global community. Functionalists are interested in eliminating the
state-system in the process of building a welfare-oriented world society
whilst acknowledging that along with international organizations, nation
states remain basic units in the international society.
Borrowing Charles Pentland's metaphor, the functionalist logic sees the
state in the context of international cooperation as "the insect in a
carnivorous plant" which while "attracted ever inward by the
benefits, it finds that behind it the avenues of retreat are progressively
blocked" (Pentland, 1973, 82). By definition, modern society generates a
myriad of technical problems that can best be resolved by experts as opposed
to politicians. A successful collaboration in one particular technical field
or functional area would lead to further collaboration in other related fields
by means of the spillover mechanism.
Governments recognize the common benefits to be gained by such cooperative
endeavours and allow for their further expansion (Viotti and Kauppi, 1993,
241). This can also allow for cooperative distribution mechanisms to balance
out some of the disparities within society, whilst recognizing, however, the
impossibility of realizing a `perfect world' (Taylor, 1990, 179).
Functionalists accept the net `high' and `low' politics dichotomy,
which is also reflected in the distinction between Community and CFSP pillars
(Mutimer, 1994, 26, Lodge, 1983b, 12). They also express their preference for
concentrating on non-political aspects in the international workshops "where
the nations shed their conflicts at the door and busy themselves only with the
cooperative use of the tools of mutual interests" which may be thwarted
by the increasing tendency to politicize all international issues (Claude,
350-353). In the words of David Mitrany, "[s]overeignty is not
effectively transferred by diplomatic formula, but via a function". The
accumulation of partial transfers of tasks from one sector to another leads
eventually to "a translation of the true seat of authority" and to
the achievement of world society (Mitrany, 1966, 35).
a.2)
The Role of the European Parliament in the Functional Model
The
definition of institution in functionalist terms, which can be easily applied
to the European Parliament, is not only of a conventional organization with
buildings and officials, but of "recognized patterns of practice around
which expectations converge" (Young, 1980, 337). In the functional model,
the European Parliament has not only to ensure a fair system of `check and
balance' within the European Union, but to accommodate the views of members
belonging to different nationality and ideology.
Although explicitly referred to the interest groups and
bureaucratic and technocratic élites, their mechanisms of interaction can be
compared to those of EP political groups, characterized by gradual changes of
MEPs' attitude and greater propensity for cooperation. The emphasis is on the
process of `social learning', whereby MEPs "are weaned away from their
allegedly irrational nationalistic impulses toward a self-reinforcing ethos of
cooperation" within their respective political groups and within the
European Parliament and become more aware of their real mutual interests (Pentland,
1973, 73, quotation 84). This slowly allows for the materialization of new
loyalties, directed at first not to the European Parliament, the common
institution, but mainly to the other members of the group. These loyalties are
not mutually exclusive and "can be `fractionated': just as a community is
the sum of its functions, so loyalty to that community is the sum of
particular loyalties to agencies in the community which satisfy functional
needs" (Pentland, 1973, 264, quotation 85). MEPs' loyalties are assumed
to be based largely on utilitarian assessment of the degree to which the
European Parliament and the political groups gratify their individual needs.
b.1)
Neofunctionalism
Set
between the rationalist and revolutionist tradition of international
relations, neofunctionalism, also known as `federal functionalism', combines
some elements from both functional and federal theories. Integration is
considered a process for the creation of a `political community' which
resembles the `supranational state' proposed by federalists (Pentland, cited
in Lodge, 1-5). Along with federalists, neofunctionalists disdain the Tönnian
model of society, the Gemeinschaft,
which embodies a community whose aim is the attainment of the general welfare
and whose roots are based on common loyalties and feeling of duty. They
replace it with the Gesellschaft
model, a pluralist type of society where conflictual interests coexist and
where cooperation and integration can be reached through a convergence of
interests (Taylor, 1983, 3-5). In the eyes of many neofunctionalists, the
objective of integration is still blurred but may lead to the establishment of
a federation where national sub-systems yield, function by function, their
authority to a central federal body (Leonardi, 1993, 5, Cameron, 1992, 28).
Although envisaging a supranational state as the end product of integration,
neofunctionalists do not exclude non-federal forms of political system and
direct their attention towards the process rather than the goal. As the
process advances, the nation state is no longer the basic unit of analysis and
transnational interactions beyond the management and control of national
governments become increasingly more frequent (Keohane, 1993, 386). Unlike the
functionalist universal tenet, neofunctionalism focuses on the establishment
of a regional integration (Mutimer, 1994, 27). However, both theories place
great emphasis on the concept of spillover,
[6]
described by Leon Lindberg as
a situation in which a given action, related to a specific goal,
creates a situation in which the original goal can be assured only by taking
further actions, which in turn create a further condition and a need for more
action, and so forth (Lindberg, 1963, 9).
The
original goal of economic integration may be achieved by furthering the
transfer of competence in other policy areas from member states to European
Community level. Ernst Haas applied the concept of spillover to the ECSC which,
by creating a common market in the sector of coal and steel production, raised
the necessity for integrating the entire energy resources of the Community,
such as nuclear energy covered by the Euratom Treaty in 1957, and gas and oil
covered by the EC Treaty, and eventually led to the establishment of a common
market for all goods and services. By the late 1960s, earlier predictions of
progress in the field of political integration failed to occur, obscuring the
general validity of this theory. Haas himself had to admit that a spillover
from economic to political sectors and a shift of authority and legitimacy
from national to supranational level were no longer automatic, but only
probable (Haas, 1966, 93). And yet, despite its imperfections, for some
authors, such as Andrew Moravcsik and Jeppe Tranholm-Mikkelsen, "[n]eofunctionalism
is by no means obsolete" (Tranholm-Mikkelsen, 1991, 19), indeed it "remains
the sole attempt to fashion a coherent and comprehensive theory of European
integration" (Moravcsik, 1991, 43-75).
b.2)
The Role of the European Parliament in the Neofunctional Model
Haas's
definition of integration extends to "the process whereby political
actors in several distinct national settings are persuaded to shift their
loyalties, expectations and political activities toward a new centre, whose
institutions possess or demand jurisdiction over the pre-existing national
states" (Haas, 1958, 16). Integration is seen as a process in which
politically significant élites "gradually redefine their interests in
terms of a regional rather than a purely national orientation" (Hodges,
1978, 245). Whenever such a constellation of interests emerges, it results in
a greater role for the central institutions and in the fostering of the
integration process. The role of these institutions, including that of
Parliament is crucial for the creation of a supranational state (Pentland,
1973, 122-123, 149). Neofunctionalists attribute great importance to élite
interaction, usually formalized in system-wide institutions. These
institutions sometimes act as arbiters, passive registrars of the results of
the conflicts inevitably arising in such a system. Political consensus
evaporates because the central institutions are not powerful enough to create
the support for further integration.
Neofunctionalists focus on the degree of alteration of élite
behaviour through learning (Sweeney, 1984, 25). Herbert Kelman's models of
attitude-change can be applied to theories of integration and in particular to
neofunctionalism and can make explicit the effects of conflict-resolution
among MEPs within their groups and within the European Parliament (Pentland,
1973, 256).
[7]
Individual attitudes are based on two components the `cognitive element'
related to the perceptions of the political world and the `affective element'
related to loyalties, values and sense of community (Pentland, 1973, 127,
129).
According to neofunctionalists, the leaders of political groups support
policies enhancing integration not out of general principles or ideologies,
but on the basis of advantages perceived in specific situations. In addition,
they may seek access to political processes operating beyond the national
level. In both cases, while MEPs' loyalties may not change fundamentally,
their perception of their political group and the European Parliament does in
view of the fact that these institutions gradually become the most important
source of benefits (Pentland, 1973, 256). Tensions occur to transnationalize
these groups, and gradually a new political outlook emerges to support such
changes. In the neofunctionalist outlook, representative assemblies are
supposed to deal with at least some areas of people's everyday life and to
establish control over crucial sectors of governments more effectively than
old-style national parliaments, which tend to lack expertise and are remote
from the central decision-making.
According
to Haas,
Parliamentarians (..) are part of the institutions which shape the
emerging European political community (..) [they] are crucial actors on the
stage of integration (..) [as potential legislators and as catalysts for
fostering the process of integration] (Haas, 1958, 390).
This
view is shared by Moravcsik who recognizes the fundamental role of the
European Parliament in fostering the process of EU integration and pressing
for further reforms by "acting above the nation-state". Yet he
rejects supranational institutionalism as a variant of neofunctionalism along
with the assumption that international institutions and transnational interest
groups play a major part in the integration process, independently from the
member states (Moravcsik, 1991, 43-75).
Neofunctional
integration theory suggests that a supranational entity like the European
Parliament, representing the `general interest' of the Union, seeks to
increase its powers in order to oppose the attempts of member states'
governments to put their own individual interests forward. Together with the
federalists, the neofunctionalists believe that central institutions gradually
would substitute national bodies in the exercise of decision-making (Ifestos,
1987, 73), by virtue of the spillover effect "across functional and to
political sectors" (Cameron, 1992, 25). The EP's acquisition of formal
powers is advocated and seen as a form of progress towards further integration.
Its compartmentalization into specialized committees, where MEPs and officials
who are experts in their various sectors work side by side, makes Parliament
the ideal combination of a political and technical institution.
Early
neofunctionalists attached particular importance to the role of political
parties in the European integration process as "carriers of values and
ideologies whose opposition, identity or convergence determines the success or
failure of a transnational ideology" (Haas, 1958, 5). Their creation and
development within the European Parliament may be seen as a way to legitimize,
expedite and foster the integration process. Party integration stems from
political and cultivated `spillover', embodying the aspiration to elevate the
élites in the European Parliament's spectrum to the status of European
parties (Hix, 1995a, 2). Neofunctionalist incremental strategy is aimed at
encouraging group interactions, to "upgrade the common interest" by
educating its members to understand the advantages of working together which
would ultimately lead to the emergence of truly transnational bodies, showing
more loyalty to the European Parliament than to any other political authority,
and to their political group rather than to the national party (Wallace and
Smith, 1995, 145).
The
integration process can be evaluated by the level of involvement of the above
institutions and their capacity for representing and combining the conflicting
interests of the various member states. The European Parliament can therefore
fulfil an important mediatory role as a permanent forum for debate,
conflict-resolution and coalition-building whereby members become acquainted
with new rules and are progressively drawn to readdress their loyalties from
the national to the central echelons (Pentland, 1973, 117).
This
view is not shared by David Marquand, who argues that neofunctionalism is
"apolitical if not anti-political; and [...] aparliamentary if not quite
anti-parliamentary. Parliaments, after all, reflect political opinion and give
expression to political demands. If integration were a technical process
rather than a political one there could be no place in it for a Parliament"
(Marquand, 1980, 1). On these lines, the powers of the Assembly of the Coal
and Steel Community and the Assembly of the European Economic Community were
extremely limited. However, as Marquand himself admits, "it seems clear
that (..) the founding fathers believed that [the parliamentary element] would
expand as time went on" (Marquand, 1980, 2). In this sense, two
fundamental neofunctionalist attributes need to be highlighted:
supranationality and political élites. The application of the principle of
supranationality would require certainly a more active role of the
`supranational institutions' in the EU decision-making process. The political
élites could find in the European Parliament the forum to lobby their
political and economic objectives.
If parties to a conference enjoy a specific and well-articulated sense
of participation, if they identify themselves completely with the procedures
and codes within which their decisions are made, they consider themselves
completely `engaged' by the results even if they do not fully concur in them (Haas,
1958, 522).
In
relation to the intra- and intergroup decision-making, Haas's three modes of
accommodation can be applied. The first consists of reaching the `minimum
common denominator', the second involves `splitting the difference' and
therefore finding a compromise between the parties, the third and final
implies `upgrading the common interest', focusing temporarily on the areas of
consensus and hoping that the areas of disagreement eventually fade (Taylor,
1983, 8, Øhrgaard, 1997, 3, 16). Of the three strategies, "the second
and the third yield the greatest amount of progress towards the goal of
political community", although only the last mode epitomizes the
veritable contribution to the integrative process (Haas, 1961, 369). As the
German MEP Otto von Habsburg emphasizes, "the learning process of
parliamentary representatives is witnessed by the fact that we have succeeded,
after some hard negotiating, in agreeing on a common text" (Habsburg,
9/10/1991, 165).
For
neofunctionalists, passionate politics and ideological clashes were to be
replaced with a problem-solving strategy, which was used effectively by the
two main groups within the European Parliament, the Socialists and the
Christian Democrats as the only way to be able to make an impact on the other
EC institutions and on decision-making. However, the neofunctionalist
motivation towards integration was considered reductionist by many since it
inferred that loyalties followed rational perceptions of interest rather that
non-rational assumptions of identity (Wallace and Smith, 1995, 146).
One
of the major concerns of neofunctionalists revolves around the process of
socialization, which results from "the combined effects of the
organizational context of decision-making, the pressures of the crisis
situation, the force of habits and procedure, the interaction with other
political actors, the awareness of a commitment or need to agree, and similar
features of the political setting, to force actors to a redefinition of their
situation, interests and methods" (Pentland, 1973, 130). In Lindberg's
words,
Participants in the activities of central institutions may develop
multiple perspectives, personal friendships, a comraderie of expertise, all of
which may reflect back upon the national governments and affect future
national policy-making (Lindberg, 1963, 10).
Lindberg's
observation may be applied to the members of the European Parliament working
in close contact within political groups, specialized committees and
inter-parliamentary delegations. This process is particularly conducive for
the purpose of this thesis since it entails the mechanisms to bring about the
required shifts of loyalties of parliamentarians to their political groups and
the European Parliament, as a result of close and continuous working
relationship (Taylor, 1983, 9, Lodge, 1989, 40-41, Tranholm-Mikkelsen, 1991,
5, 14, Øhrgaard, 1997, 3, 15-17). Neofunctionalist
theory discerns between the `cognitive' and `affective' factors of individual
attitudes. The former relates to the perception of the political world, the
expectation concerning the sources of interest-fulfilment. The latter, which
is less `rational' and is connected with loyalties, values and the sense of
community, is favoured by neofunctionalists. Given the strong orientation
towards utilitarian satisfaction and the various sources of such satisfaction,
political attitudes of individuals tend to be multiple and internally divided
(Lindberg, 1963, 6). Hence, shifts of loyalties and expectations are not
deemed to be either total or simultaneous, but gradual.
c.1)
Pluralism
Pluralist/transactionalist
or communication school
[8]
can be placed within the realm of rationalism in both its descriptive and
normative elements for its emphasis on `international and institutionalized
intercourse'. Karl Deutsch, its main architect, envisaged as the objective of
integration the realization of a `political community' consisting of an
international system of developed nation states which, albeit without a common
government, is characterized by a high level of international communications
and transactions. Closer diplomatic and commercial contacts foster "a
sense of shared community and trust" which make war between members
inconceivable (Wallace and Smith, 1995, 153). However, there is no evidence
that those institutions emerging to promote cross-border cooperation and
communication, represent the "embryo of a supranational state" (Pentland,
1973, 29).
Non-state actors represent a focal point in the pluralist paradigm, for
their interactions within the states and other non-state actors operating
across national borders. States are not integrated entities, but are composed
of bureaucracies, interest groups and individuals that attempt to influence
foreign policy through competition, coalition building, conflict and
compromise. Against this background, pluralists challenge the notion of the
state as a rational actor because, to establish a consensus or, at least, a
minimum winning coalition, is a process different in kind from what is usually
meant to be a rational and optimal decision.
On
pluralist assumptions, integration reflects the "attainment within a
territory of a `sense of Community'", by turning previously separate
units into components of a coherent system and by fostering transactions
between societies and changes in public attitudes within societies. And yet,
there is no requirement for the abolition of the nation state nor for the
creation of a unitary supranational state (Deutsch et al., 1957, cited in
Ifestos, 75). Within a pluralistic
security community, individual governments retain their legal independence
(Hodges, 1978, 244). The process of adjustment in various spheres seems to
constitute the terminal situation and not a process leading to a
`supranational state', although pluralists prefer the community-model to the
state-model advocated by many federalists (Taylor, 1975, 13).
c.2)
The Role of the
European Parliament in the Pluralist Model
According
to the pluralists, the telos of
integration consists of "an international system of developed nations"
with no central governmental institutions. They admit the possibility of
attaining in future a supranational European dimension, but deny that this
might result from popular or parliamentary clout since governments still hold
the monopoly over the destiny of their respective countries. Although
designating the direct relationship between citizens and the European
Parliament, pluralists acknowledge the restricted popular and therefore
parliamentary involvement in international politics. In brief, in the
pluralist paradigm, "no (..) government is likely to put itself in a
position of being swept out of power by a surge of popular internationalist
[or Europeanist] feeling" (Pentland, 1973, 33, 38, quotation 63).
Deutsch
envisaged an increase in international communications and transactions that
would encourage "a sense of shared community and trust". In
particular, he stressed the importance of socio-psychological factors in
community building, also associating loyalties with the capacity to provide
security (Hodges, 1972, 19). This emphasis on the integrative effects of
communications between members and its socio-psychological aspects can be
easily applied to the political groups and to the European Parliament as a
whole.
d.1)
Consociationalism
The
term `consociationalism', coined by Arend Lijphart in 1968 and resurrected by
Hans Daalder in 1974, refers to a model for deeply divided societies, a
speculative instrument for solving disputes of inter-ethnic nature and a new
pattern of international integration which has been applied by Paul Taylor to
the European integration process (Taylor, 1990c, 172-173, 176). The theory,
drawn from the domain of comparative politics, focuses on two main concepts:
`consociation', regarding vertical relations between the states and the
collectivity, and `symbiosis', regarding horizontal relations between the
states (Taylor, 1996, 79).
The
peculiarity of consociationalism lies in its ability to combine an advanced
regional integration with the survival of existing national sovereignties. Its
strategy focuses not on mitigating antagonisms between nations, but creating a
framework within which dissenting minorities gain some degree of autonomy. The
European Union can be regarded as a case of `cohabitation' of sovereign states
which although preserving their distinctive cultures deliberately replace
competitive political attitude with what Gerald R. McDaniel defines as
`politics of smoothness' (Glidningspolitik)
or the practice of accommodation and compromise aimed at reaching mutual
understanding (MacDaniel, 1963, cited in Chryssochoou, 1994, 20-21).
d.2)
The Role of the European Parliament in the Consociational Model
Following
the consociational logic, the European Parliament, in its holistic approach,
could host diverse interests by giving birth to a new socio-political entity
which goes beyond the simple sum of its components. The ambition of creating
transnational political groups is not within the scope of consociationalism
which instead envisages the formation of multinational groups that can still
maintain their political unity even without surmounting national barriers. The
model allows for MEPs to coexist and collaborate within a group without the
need of sacrificing their national identity to the accomplishment of their
respective interests, and contends that despite language, religious and ethnic
differences, a certain level of group cohesion can be achieved.
`Symbiosis',
used synonymously with `mutualism', refers to a harmonious partnership between
different entities in which the `symbionts' eventually benefit from the
association. It implies a state of affairs whereby two or more actors learn to
live with each other, test their strengths for cooperative interactions and,
if necessary, reconcile a welter of distinct and often conflicting interests
in a mutually acceptable and advantageous manner rather than embarking on an
exhaustive competition at the expense of the others' vital interests (Chryssochoou,
1994, 19-20).
Efficiency
in the EP policy-making and activities can be achieved, according to this
theory, by establishing a positive-sum game at PG and EP levels to accommodate
both supranational, national and ideological predicaments, paving the way
towards the formation of consociational partnership: an elaborate system of
cooperative subcultures which practically means the achievement of a balance
of advantages and costs for all the participants involved in regional
decision-making, irrespective of their national, subnational or supranational
origins. This would reconcile two opposing necessities: `democracy'
underpinning the need for the expression of all various opinions and
`efficiency' relating to the capacity of the segments to formulate policies by
hammering out agreements through the practice of appeasement and compromise.
Revolutionists/universalists
[9]
identify themselves with the moral unity of international society claiming to
be totally committed to its achievement through the establishment of
transnational social bonds between citizens of the various states and the
gradual overcoming of the absolute supremacy of the state and of interstate
barriers (Halliday, 1994, 99). Universal renovation and radical transformation
are constant attributes of this doctrine, which is not exclusively addressed
to states but to international organizations, transnational actors and their
interactions. In antithesis with the realists, revolutionists reject the
artificial dichotomy between `high' and `low' politics emphasizing that
economic factors serve to explain the dynamics of the international system (Viotti
and Kauppi, 1993, 8, 10-11, 18).
Revolutionism/Universalism in the Context of European integration
a.1)
Federalism
A
myriad of interpretations surrounds the concept of federalism, as reflected in
its various theoretical underpinnings as well as in the political branches of
federalist thinking. The moderate and more pragmatic branch falls perfectly
within the rationalist school of thought for the emphasis on `international
and institutionalized intercourse'. The radical and idealistic branch recalls
aspects of the revolutionist/universalist tradition of Althusius and Rousseau
with its intention of transcending the conventional nation states and its
ambition of transforming international realities by going beyond the
construction of a society of states.
To this utopian vein belong writers such as Guy Héraud and C.L. Kohr who
believe that by encouraging a new common political culture it is possible
ultimately to create a world society and government (Harrison, 1974, 45).
Integration is seen as a dramatic, revolutionary process as "the time
becomes ripe for change" (Taylor, 1975, 12). This view is reiterated with
vigour by Denis de Rougemont who insists that to establish this model of
federation is "the primary, long overdue and decisive task, the real leap,
the revolutionary and creative action without which we shall not leave the
present plane of impossibilities" (de Rougemont, 1967, 348).
Nevertheless,
federalism shares the realist premise of the birth of the Hobbesian Leviathan,
a supreme ruler entrusted with the authority to maintain order and peace by
the people in order to escape from the dangers of the anarchic `state of
nature' (Pentland, 1973, 147).
Some
authors, such as Murray Forsyth, focus on federalism
as a type of government founded upon a foedus or treaty between states.
It is the process by which a number of separate states raise themselves by
contract to the threshold of being one state (Forsyth, 1981, 2).
In
this context, the nation state is seen as a basic political unit that needs to
be accommodated rather than abolished. By contrast, for others such as Héraud
the nation state is nothing but a `historic accident' which rational federal
development would supersede. He visualizes a Europe des ethnies composed of collectivities naturally united by
language and other cultural traditions and much more equal and manageable
entities that the nation states (Harrison, 1974, 45). This view is based on
the Kantian tradition of International Relations which stresses moral
imperatives enjoining not simply cooperation among states but rather the
overthrow of the system of states and its replacement by a cosmopolitan
society where the European federation is a step as well as a required catalyst
(Bull, 1977, 1995, 25). Federal Europe can be created "on the widespread
destruction and disillusionment brought about by the war by providing an
attractive alternative to the rebuilding of the nation-state system with its
inherent rivalries" (de Rougemont, 1965 cited in Hodges, 1978, 241). And
yet, while representing the first and most well-known approach of European
integration, federalism has been often denied recognition as a real theory in
the traditional sense, for its explicit normative content and for privileging
the description of the final goal over the scientific analysis of method and
procedure (Mutimer, 1994, 8). The final condition of integration presents an
alternative to "national atavism and insularity" by proposing the
creation of a federal union among previously sovereign powers (O'Neill, 1996,
23).
While
agreeing in principle on the goal of European integration, federalists
disagreed on the methods to be employed to achieve a fully-fledged federation.
The maximalists, among whom was Altiero Spinelli, author of the 1941
federalist Ventotene Manifesto and founder of the Mouvement
Fédéraliste Européen (MFE), believed that European integration was a
process to be achieved through political means (Harrison, 1974, 49). More
specifically, maximalists intended to promote an international campaign aimed
at persuading public opinion and mobilizing political forces which would
culminate with the setting up of a Constituent Assembly, elected by universal
suffrage (Marquand, 1980, 1). This assembly would draft a federal constitution
endowing powers to the central government with regard to budget, foreign
policy and defence, including provisions for safeguarding fundamental and
minority rights. This text would be finally submitted either to national
parliaments for ratification or directly to European citizens by means of
popular referenda. Minimalists gathered under the Action
Européen Fédéraliste (AUF), to which eventually Spinelli converted,
took the more pragmatic view that the federal goal could be achieved by
gradual steps through the establishment of organizations such as the ECSC,
EURATOM and European Economic Community (Harrison, 1974, 50). This dichotomy
inherent to federalism makes it rather difficult to place this approach within
the mainstream of IR theory.
The
great merit of federalism rests in the ability to reconcile the integration
process with the necessity of preserving diversity, an element which
represents a precondition of any kind of integration in Europe and of the
prerogatives of the European Parliament. By dividing political power between
central and local powers, the federal model represents a very attractive
strategy for uniting groups of states possessing diverse interests and
satisfies the often mutually exclusive criteria of efficiency and democracy (Hodges,
1978, 241). Within a federal union, not only national, but also regional and
local interests are duly represented. This emphasis on model privileges
decentralization and, therefore, conforms to the logic of subsidiarity, a
principle which Britain has promoted and which is now enshrined in the Treaty
on European Union (Mutimer, 1994, 18). The essence of federalism lies in the
decentralization of power and not, as is wrongly perceived especially in
Britain, in "a greedy form of government in which central government
progressively deprives [...] national governments of power, making them
subordinate to the central authorities" (Lodge, 1983b, 9). According to
Juliet Lodge, the hostility of certain politicians to the idea of a federal
evolution of the European Union may often arise from ignorance and
misunderstanding of its main principles.
a.2)
The Role of the European Parliament in the Federal Model
Federalists
give a salient position to the European Parliament which represents the focal
point for the integration process for its ability of promoting the European
idea and offering a platform for discussion (Spinelli, 1966, 154)
[10]
and embodies the Lower House of the European federation, comparable to the US
House of Representatives or the German Bundestag
(Lodge, 1983b, 9-10). Together with the Council, which would become a
legislative Upper House, the EP would rule "with the executive over all
the spheres of activity placed under its control by the federal constitution"
(Haas, 1958, 394). Federalists demand the expansion of direct and indirect
democratic controls over the execution of foreign policy and the realization
of the democratic system of `check and balance' in the form of greater
parliamentary powers at European, national and regional levels.
In
line with the Kantian perspective, the EP's vocation is to promote a "European
perspective and not one that would be only the sum of the national ones"
(Spinelli cited in Burgess, 1989, 135). This transnationality/supranationality
element characterizing the federal approach is central to this doctoral thesis
which intends to test the feasibility of this goal within the EP and the PGs
through an investigation into two case studies, the Gulf and Yugoslav crises.
For federalists, common needs or fears have the effect of producing common
perception of the sort of political solution required, as well as the common
loyalties to support it. Communication and interaction constitute the basis of
a collective learning process towards an increased awareness, trust and
loyalty between the members of the groups, "assumed to be
self-reinforcing, rather like the ascending spiral of `escalation'" (Pentland,
1973, 252). Federalists assign great relevance to the presence of `political
will' and `élites' favourable to a shift of powers from national to
supranational institutions (Ifestos, 1987, 71). However, they allow for
multiple levels of political allegiance, so that Members of the European
Parliament can remain loyal to their constituency, nation and EU which, albeit
of varying intensities, are not incompatible or conflicting. The approach
presupposes that the desirability of European Union is widely accepted and
envisages the establishment of new habits of collaboration between groups, new
decision-making mechanisms as well as the emergence of new attitudes or
mentalities, but recognizes that the shift of loyalties towards the centre is
not total (Pentland, 172-174). This engrenage
differs from neofunctionalist spillover
in so far as it lacks the latter's dynamic characteristics. For Reginald
Harrison, it implies "the enmeshment of member units and the `locking-in'
of whatever integrative steps are achieved. It is likely to be limited in
scope. It does not assume continuous progress and is not, therefore,
invalidated by the conservative forces of adjustment which may be asserted in
response to change" (Harrison, 1974, 244).
The
establishment of central institutions, endowed with certain autonomous powers,
an effective decision-making process and democratic control, which would lead
to the formation of genuine European political parties, is necessary for the
fostering of the integration process (Harrison, 1974, 244).
The
endeavour of locating European integration theories within the wider
theoretical spectrum of International Relations has proven to be ambitious and
challenging, mainly due to the difficulty of incorporating such a variety of
concepts, often overlapping, within clear-cut classifications. The main
theoretical assumptions relevant to European integration do not always remain
in a fixed position within the three IR traditions since they often combine
elements of different schools of thought. This is partly because, as Hedley
Bull states,
[t]he modern international system reflects all three of the elements
singled out respectively by the Hobbesian, the Kantian and the Grotian
traditions: the element of war and struggle for power among states, the
element of transnational solidarity and conflict, cutting across the divisions
among states, and the element of co-operation and regulated intercourse among
states. In different historical phases of the states system, in different
geographical theatres of its operation, and in the policies of different
states and statesmen, one of these three elements may predominate over the
others (Bull, 1977, 1995, 39).
And
yet, such an attempt has been made with the aim of generating a debate that
has been neglected for too long in academic literature. Another difficulty
arises from the fact that "the term `integration' glitters with a
multiplicity of meanings" (Abelshauser, 1994, 1), ranging from the
creation of a fully-fledged federation of the states of Europe to the
establishment of a loose concert of independent states: the Gaullist Europe des Patries. While the former stresses the totality of
central institutions with a great emphasis on the position of the European
Parliament, the latter focuses on nationally-based centres of decision-making,
denying any role to the European Parliament.
European
integration was strategically negotiated, therefore, as a `journey to an
unknown destination' to enable member states' governments as well as the
proponents of the various integration theories to interpret freely the real
meaning of this nebulous term. The final hindrance to the explanation of
European integration also stems from the fact that it is not a single
definable event, but a "continuous series of processes" not
comparable to other regional or international organizations (Harrison, 1974,
22-23). Any search for a self-contained formula able to describe theoretically
the evolution of this phenomenon is "doomed to fail" as its
interpretation requires recourse to different notions and analytical
methodologies from social science and history (Hill, 1994, 104-105). It is,
therefore, not surprising that no single IR and integration theories can
explain adequately the role of the EP and political groups in the integration
process. Depending on one's adherence to the realist or federalist perspective,
the EP's functions will vary enormously. Aspects of two contesting approaches
under the banners of federalism and neofunctionalism are particularly relevant
in terms of maximization of the EP's competence. The process of
transnationalization within the European Parliament and its political groups
can be seen in the revolutionist perspective of overcoming national barriers,
overthrowing the system of states and replacing it with a universal community.
Both paradigms accord a vital role to the European Parliament, retaining the
view that the transfer of decision-making from the national governments to the
central institutions is crucial to the integration process. Functionalism,
neofunctionalism, pluralism and consociationalism recognize that, through a
`learning-by-association' process, members of the European Parliament develop
a stronger cooperative ethos which
can modify both their perceptions of political life and their feelings toward
each other. They all perceive political groups, which are "composites of
subnational, national and supranational elements" as generators of
attitudes enhancing integration, although only rarely is this notion expressed
in a theoretically coherent fashion (Pentland, 1973, quotation 222, 242, 251,
262).
An
in-depth analysis of the traditional integration theory has largely been
overlooked in recent years. In particular, the learning and adaption processes
within the European Parliament need to be filtered into any theoretical
account of the integration process. The learning of cooperative habits
stressed by functionalism, the effects of élite-interactions indicated by
pluralism, the formative influence of institutions emphasized by federalism,
the socialization process analysed by neofunctionalism and the phenomenon of
symbiosis emphasized by consociationalism - all of these notions that rely on
similar assumptions represent useful conceptual tools for an understanding of
MEPs' interactions. Pluralists and functionalists rely upon the generalized
process of `social learning' while neofunctionalists focus their interest on a
more restricted process of attitude change among those individuals within a
political group or within the Europarliamentary arena characterized by an
active reorientation towards political life and by a high rate of political
participation. This factor, which is examined in the second part of the thesis,
is a crucial indicator of the achievement of the overall process of
integration.
The
application of socio-psychological insights to the study of political
integration can be helpful with regard to MEP behaviour within the political
groups within the European Parliament, often neglected by theorists of
integration. The extent to which élite attitudes are reliable indicators of
the probable direction of integration depends on such factors as the internal
cohesion of the groups, the structure of the decision-making institutions, the
general distribution of power in the institution concerned, and the degree to
which particular issues such as foreign policy affect deep-seated values or
feelings among the general public. In addition, regular contacts among MEPs of
different nationalities, either within political groups or the European
Parliament, can generate the forging of `European' attitudes and are important
factors in enhancing integration.
In summary, the previous theoretical survey has been helpful in reaching the conclusion that, while no single approach seems to capture the phenomenon adequately, a number of elements derived from integration theories can assist us in the search for an explanation of the expanding role of the European Parliament in EU policy-making and the evolution of the political groups. The Europarliamentary arena and the various political groups operate as a living laboratory, where an experiment has been undertaken - that of placing together members representing various national and political approaches with the aim of studying their interactions.
[1] The most comprehensive and, at the same time, detailed surveys of the traditional set of European integration theories are those of Pentland (1973), Harrison (1974) Taylor (1983) and George (1985). A more recent effort at reviewing the main theoretical contributions with extracts of their key authors is offered by O'Neill (1996). However, these books devote little or no space to the remit of the European Parliament and its transnational political groups in the various International Relations and European integration theories. The role of the political groups are often subsumed into the general analysis on interest groups. Corbett (1998) attempts to redress this omission to some extent by examining the role of the European Parliament in light of the following approaches to European integration: constituent federalism, gradualist federalism, neofunctionalism, interdependence theory and intergovernmentalism. He also looks at the expectations within the academic and political circle of the elected Parliament by also briefly referring to the development of political groups inside the EP arena. Webb (1983) makes only a brief reference to the Parliament in her review of integration theories. Other books focus on the parliamentary powers in the federal model (Spinelli, 1957, 1958, 1960, 1972; Wheare, 1963). Others touch only briefly on the place of parliamentary developments in the federal and neofunctional logics (Marquand, 1980). An attempt to study the possible role of the European Parliament and the political parties in the European integration process by using neofunctionalist theory is made by Sweeney (1984). And yet, the most accurate analysis of the political groups remains that undertaken by Haas (1958) who devotes Chapter IV of his book to the supranational political parties in the ECSC Common Assembly. Several studies including that by Geoffrey and Pippa Pridham (1981) focus on the historical development or on the organization and working of the political groups, neglecting however their role in integration theories. The historical evolution of the EC underlying the emergence of the various theoretical approaches over time has been outlined by William Wallace and Julie Smith (1995).
[2] Although agreeing in principle on the trilogy of philosophical thought, Martin Wight and Hedley Bull used a different terminology. Wight's classification consists of realism, rationalism and revolutionism while Bull's classification includes realism, internationalism and universalism.
[3] Game theory relates to the interactions between at least two actors, while cooperative theory focuses on the dynamics of a concerted decision-making process achieved by establishing coalitions.
[4]
Besides
Wight and Bull's classifications, Viotti and Kauppi distinguish three
streams of political thought: realism, pluralism and globalism (Viotti and
Kauppi, 1993). Many of the features of rationalism referred to within this
article can also be found within Viotti and Kauppi's definition of pluralism.
[5] As Charles Pentland notices, not all functionalists agree with this determinist view and, in particular with R. Lemaignen's belief that European integration represents a subsequent phase of the `irreversible' phenomenon of nation absorbing province absorbing tribe (Lemaignen, 1964, 209-210 cited in Pentland, 1973, 65).
[6] George (1991, 21-24) introduces a distinction between `functional' and `political spillover', while Tranholm-Mikkelsen (1991, 4-6) identifies three kinds of spillover: `functional', `political' and `cultivated'. The latter's distinction is followed by Hix (1995a, 2).
[7] Kelman's analysis includes three levels of attitude-change: compliance, identification and internalization. Compliance operates through the promise of economic, political or symbolic reward, identification occurs mainly through the satisfaction of psychological needs and internalization results from the enhancement of personal values, but the main external stimulus is likely to be new information gained through communication or interaction.
[8] Pluralist, transactionalist and communication school are terms used to refer to Karl Deutch's integration theory. Some scholars such as Charles Pentland (1973) call it pluralism, others, including William Wallace and Julie Smith (1995), refer to it as transactionalism and, finally, Laura Cram (1996) speaks of transactionalism/communication school.
[9] Terminology used respectively by Martin Wight and Hedley Bull.
ã Copyright 2000. Jean Monnet Chair of European Comparative Politics
Donatella M. Viola, London School of Economics